Friday, October 14, 2011


All there is are Lies
All there is is Pain
All there is is suffer in the name Faith
Barbaric shadow all over the land


I Shocked as I see 
Mindless Creatures 
Angry Creator , Bloodthirsty Throne


All there is are Lies
All there is is Hate
All there is is Brutality against each other
Its all there was, Its all there'll ever be


Poisoned Truth , Colored Lies 
Heaven of Lies ,Abyss of Desire 


All Raise against it 
All Up against the serpent 
These Lies are a curse , Their Truth is Unclean
Your poisoned throne will fall 
Our Mind is Our Weapon 


You can Close my Hands , 
You can Close my Mouth
But my Mind will Fly 
Your Barbaric Reign will Fall

By : Ahmad TBP

Monday, October 3, 2011

Iranian Society


Iranian Society

The invasion of the private sphere in Iran: individual, family, community and state
By: Mehrangiz Kar, 2003


The Islamic regime that governs Iran constantly violates the private domain of the Iranian citizen through religious and legal means. The intrusion of political power into the private lives of citizens is characteristic of totalitarian regimes. In Iran the regime has disguised the intrusion as a religious ethics requirement and justifies it by cloaking it in a religious guise.

The private sphere of those labeled "dissidents" is more threatened than that of other citizens. Using the legal and religious laws the regime has adopted, government agencies have brought all aspects of the private life of dissidents, critics, artists, and political activists under surveillance. For instance, listening to the telephone conversations of dissidents is a widespread practice, allowing the authorities to monitor and control dissidents' private interaction and communication. Through these methods the regime conspires against dissidents, accusing them of illegal sexual activities, apostasy, and spying. This infringement of citizens' private lives by the police and the regime's security forces by falsely accusing them of ideological and sexual crimes, clearly violates Article 37 of the Iranian constitution, which calls for the presumption of innocence.

Violation of the private sphere is not limited to dissidents but extends to all Iranian citizens. Since 1979, technocrats have legitimized this intrusion based on an appeal to Islamic laws. They have drawn on the religious interpretations of political clergy who are connected to political power in Iran to pass legislation that blatantly contradicts the principles of freedom and human rights. The ruling clergy thus puts its stamp of approval on the systematic violation of citizens' private lives. The constitution of the Islamic Republic that was adopted in 1981 envisioned that the country's laws and policies would not contravene Sharia, or religious law (this is stated in Article 4 and 94). This means that the rights formulated in the 30 articles of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights cannot be incorporated in Iranian laws--and this also means that government agencies have free rein to carry out their intrusions and oppression.

The application of Sharia makes possible the control of the private sphere of citizens' lives. In this paper I will discuss two legal means by virtue of which the regime keeps private lives of citizens under surveillance. These are: 1- legalized inquisition; and 2- the obligation to enjoin the good and forbid the evil.[1]

Legalized Inquisition
Even though Article 23 of the constitution of the Islamic Republic of Iran forbids inquisition, the regime actively carries out the practice. The legal and political architectonics of the Islamic Republic justifies inquisition as necessary for the protection of Islamic and revolutionary values. And the scope of religious government is so vast that it allows for the investigation of every aspect of an individual's private beliefs. A few examples follow.

Individuals trying to register a political party or cultural organization or who want to obtain a license to publish a newspaper must submit to inquisition. To register a political party or to run for office requires a thorough investigation of one's private convictions. The approval of an applicant depends on a positive evaluation by the administrative agencies. During the evaluation process the agencies not only inspect the applicant's past but also his or her personal beliefs, private thoughts, and family history. If in any of these areas there is any evidence that the applicant is not committed to the doctrine of velayat-e faqih, or rule by the clergy, his or her application is rejected. The conduct of inquisition for the purposes of political and cultural activities is so rigorous that even the pious are required to prove their faithfulness. Of course, the measure of faithfulness is always how faithful one is to velayat-e faqih. Those whose conduct reveals a critical view of that doctrine or evidence that puts into doubt their absolute loyalty to the regime are branded as infidels, counter-revolutionaries, and spies, and their candidacy for an office or their application for a license rejected. To keep such individuals under surveillance, they are followed, their phone lines are tapped, and their homes inspected. The warrant for such intrusions into the public's private domain of life is, of course, granted by the clergy connected to the political power of the velayat-e faqih.

Religious minorities, other than those who are Christian, Jewish, or Zoroastrian, are not allowed to practice their religious beliefs. The regime assumes as its undisputed right the ability to conduct an inquisition of religious minorities and prescribe limits on their lives. Baha'is are a case in point. They are kept under constant surveillance and control and are denied opportunities for higher education and employment. When they are victims of crime or even killed they or their families are denied justice. From the regime's perspective they are considered dispensable or "deserving to die" (mahdur al-dam); see Article 226 and subsection 2 of Article 295 of the criminal code.

Similarly, the punishment of a Muslim who converts to another religion is death. This and other techniques of control carried out by the regime's various agencies allow the Islamic Republic to manage the lives those opposed to its rule. As soon as these agencies gather enough evidence to accuse a dissident of infidelity, the dissidents is declared "deserving of murder" and killed. To kill an infidel who deserves to be killed has no punishment and the law allows fanatics to kill those who have converted from Islam without fear of punishment.

Undercover agents from the Ministry of Information have committed serial killings of many opposition figures and have not faced prosecution. These killings have been prefaced by intrusion into the most private areas of the dissidents' lives--private relations, opinions, actions, and expressions were scrutinized for years.

All Iranian citizens live under a system that determines opportunities for social advancement on the basis of appeals to legal and religious authorities. Thus, in the area of employment, an individual's preferences and abilities are often ignored in favor of a test of the candidate's loyalty to the regime--a test that is carded out by examining the individual's private life. The undercover agents conduct a thorough background check that includes visits to all places that the candidate has lived during his or her life and interviews with all the candidate's local contacts. The local investigation even includes the kind of hejab of the women of the candidate's family.[2] The candidate's loyalty to velayat-e faqih is the mark of his loyalty to Islam and the revolution.

Enjoining Good and Forbidding Evil
The obligation of enjoining the good and forbidding the evil is an uncompromising Islamic principle. In the Islamic Republic, Sharia has become a legal means to intrude violently into the lives of the people and oppress them. The imperative of enjoining the good and forbidding the evil is used to control women's hejab, gatherings, associations, parties, weddings, dating, and the consumption of alcoholic beverages. The numerous inspection agencies believe they have the right to invade the lives of private individuals and attack their personal preferences. Such invasions are, of course, justified by appeal to the imperative of enjoining the good and the forbidding evil as stated in Article 8 of the constitution, which grounds the laws governing the rights and duties of the security forces and police. A few examples of these laws, which have led to the violent treatment of citizens by the police and judiciary system, will be discussed.

For women, choice of clothing is regulated. All women are required to wear the hejab and the law penalizes those who do not by imprisonment or considerable fine (see the relevant section under Article 638 of the Islamic criminal code).

Choice of spouse is also regulated. The father and paternal ancestors are allowed to arrange for their children or grand-children to be wed before the children reach the legal age for marriage (see the section under Article 1041 of the civil law). A young women is allowed--as long as she is still a virgin--to marry only with the permission of her father, grandfather, or the court. If a woman marries without the required permission, a court will nullify marriage, regardless of the age of the couple (see Articles 1143 and 1144 of the civil law). Moreover, the marriage of a Muslim woman with a non-Muslim man is not allowed (under Article 1054 of the civil law). The marriage of an Iranian woman with a foreigner is only allowed with the permission of the government (under Article 1060 of civil law). A man can divorce his wife anytime he so desires (under Article 1133), but mere desire is not enough for a woman to divorce her husband (under Article 1130). Furthermore, a man may marry up to four wives (according to Article 942 of the civil law).

When it comes to sexual satisfaction in marriage, women, by law, are always required to meet the sexual needs of their husbands. Women's psychological needs and readiness are not taken into account by the lawmakers. Consequently, women's sexual satisfaction as the most private area of their existence is controlled by the governing regime (see Article 1106 of the civil law). Women who do not attend to their husband's needs, according to these laws, can be punished with severe fines (see Article 1108 of the civil law).

Free sexual relationships are considered crimes and are severely punished (see Article 63 of the criminal code). The punishment for a man or woman condemned of adultery is 100 lashes (according to Article 88 of the criminal code). Adultery may even be punished by death when a Muslim woman and a non-Muslim man are involved, in which case the man is condemned to death (see Article 82 of the criminal code). In cases where the man and woman are married, their punishment, according to Article 83 of the criminal code, is stoning.

Women's romantic and sexual preferences are thus severely limited by law. By bestowing upon men the right to have multiple spouses, the regime in effect has institutionalized women's disadvantage and brought gender relations under its legal control.

Homosexuality is considered a crime and those who commit homosexual acts may be punished. If two women who are not related to each other are found naked under a cover they are to be punished by lashing (see Article 134 of the criminal code). Lesbianism is punishable by 100 lashes, and if the act is repeated up to four times the accused can be condemned to death (see Article 131 of criminal code). Similarly, if two unrelated men are found naked under a cover their punishment is 99 lashes (Article 123 of criminal code) and if their conduct is repeated four times both can be put to death (Article 122 of criminal code). If two men are found guilty of engaging in a homosexual act, both are to be put to death, according to Articles 109 and 110 of the criminal code.

A man and a woman who socialize with one another without any sexual relations occurring may be punished by 74 lashes (Article 638 of the criminal code). This crime is called Fe'l haram or a "taboo act" and it even includes handshakes between men and women. Private parties at which women may be in attendance are scrutinized to determine whether the women are dressed "correctly" and whether alcohol is being consumed or Western music is being played (the consumption of alcohol and enjoying one's preferred but unsanctioned music is a crime; anyone found guilty of drinking alcohol may be punished by lashing, as may be those who have been found listening to Western music, although fines or imprisonment could also be meted out). The private sphere of an Iranian citizen's life, whether a man or a woman, Muslim or non-Muslim, is tumultuous because of the fear of invasion and violation by the regime's agencies.

http://www.iranchamber.com/society/articles/iinvasion_private_sphere_iran.php 



Saturday, October 1, 2011

Sacred Lies


Nothing left , dried land , rivers of blood , unknown abyss 
Failed system , sacred lies , control , blindly obedience
Blind minds , deaf thoughts 
Throne of death , Throne of blood 
Religion of lie , lies of old , empty promises 
Unclean reign


Mother of death , mother of all lies 
All mankind doomed to its will 
Dawn of blind , dawn of brutality
Angry God , bloodthirsty decrees


Old Lies ,
Blind Beliefs
False Light 
Blinded Justice


Empty promises , unclean beliefs , serpents of desire
Unholy throne of a masked jackal
Coming down to earth ,the wolf , the false god 


Unclean divine , serpent of darkness 
Black darkness surrounding the truth 
Promises have been made , lies , all lies , to control 
Wiped out truth , superseded lies 
Blood of vengeance running in veins 
They came to kill , End of time is near , 
They will raise the fears they will root into hearts 
Manipulated Reality


Old Lies ,
False Redemption 
Divine Crimes 
False Divines
Sacred Lies


By : Ahmad TBP


Wednesday, September 7, 2011

Atheism and Agnosticism

author = Smart, J. J. C.
title = Atheism and Agnosticism
booktitle = The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
editor = Edward N. Zalta, 

Atheism and Agnosticism
First published Tue Mar 9, 2004; substantive revision Mon Aug 8, 2011 
The main purpose of this article is to explore the differences between atheism and agnosticism, and the relations between them. The task is made more difficult because each of these words are what Wittgenstein called ‘family resemblance’ words. That is, we cannot expect to find a set of necessary and sufficient conditions for their use. Their use is appropriate if a fair number of the conditions are satisfied. Moreover even particular members of the families are often imprecise, and sometimes almost completely obscure. Sometimes a person who is really an atheist may describe herself, even passionately, as an agnostic because of unreasonable generalised philosophical scepticism which would preclude us from saying that we know anything whatever except perhaps the truths of mathematics and formal logic. 

1. Atheism 
‘Atheism’ means the negation of theism, the denial of the existence of God. I shall here assume that the God in question is that of a sophisticated monotheism. The tribal gods of the early inhabitants of Palestine are of little or no philosophical interest. They were essentially finite beings, and the god of one tribe or collection of tribes was regarded as good in that it enabled victory in war against tribes with less powerful gods. Similarly the Greek and Roman gods were more like mythical heroes and heroines than like the omnipotent, omniscient and good God postulated in mediaeval and modern philosophy. As the Romans used the word, ‘atheist’ could be used to refer to theists of another religion, notably the Christians, and so merely to signify disbelief in their own mythical heroes. The word ‘theism’ exhibits family resemblance in another direction. For example should a pantheist call herself an atheist? Or again should belief in Plato's Form of the Good or in John Leslie's idea of God as an abstract principle that brings value into existence count as theism (Leslie 1979)? Let us consider pantheism. At its simplest, pantheism can be ontologically indistinguishable from atheism. Such a pantheism would be belief in nothing beyond the physical universe, but associated with emotions of wonder and awe similar to those that we find in religious belief. I shall not consider this as theism. Probably the theologian Paul Tillich was a pantheist in little more than this minimal sense and his characterising God as the ground of being has no clear meaning. The unanswerable question ‘Why is there anything at all?’ may give us mystical or at any rate dizzy feelings but such feelings do not differentiate the pantheist from the atheist. However there are stronger forms of pantheism which do differentiate the pantheist from the atheist (Levine, 1994). For example the pantheist may think that the universe as a whole has strongly emergent and also mind-like qualities. Not emergent merely in the weak sense that a radio receiver's ability to receive signals from distant stations might be said to be emergent because it is not a mere jumble of components (Smart 1981). The components have to be wired together in a certain way, and indeed the workings of the individual components can be explained by the laws of physics. Contrast this with a concept of emergence that I shall call ‘strong emergence’. C. D. Broad in his Scientific Thought (Broad 1923) held that the chemical properties of common salt could not even in principle be deduced from those of sodium and chlorine separately, at the very time at which the quantum theory of the chemical bond was beginning to be developed. Though the mind has seemed to some to be strongly emergent from its physical basis, it can be argued that developments in the philosophy of mind, cognitive science and neuroscience favour weak emergence only. One strong form of pantheism ascribes mental properties to the cosmos. If the weak sense of emergence was adopted we would be faced with the question of whether the universe looks like a giant brain. Patently it does not. Samuel Alexander asserted, rather than argued, that mentality strongly emerged from space-time, and then that at some future time there will emerge a new and at present hardly imaginable level which he called ‘deity’ (Alexander 1927). It is hard to tell whether such an implausible metaphysics should be classified as as pantheism or as theism. Certainly such a deity would not be the infinite creator God of orthodox theism. A. N. Whitehead, too, had a theory of an emergent deity, though with affinities to Platonism, which he saw as the realm of potentiality and therefore he connected the atemporal with the contingent temporal deity (Whitehead 1929). Such views will not deliver, however implausibly, more than a finite deity, not the God of core theism. God would be just one more thing in the universe, however awesome and admirable. The weak form of pantheism accepts that the physical universe is all and eschews strong emergence. Sometimes the weak form of pantheism is rhetorically disguised as theism, with God characterised as ‘absolute depth’ or some equally baffling expression, as by Paul Tillich. At any rate, whether or not we accept pantheism as a sort of theism, what we mean by ‘atheism’ will vary according to what in the dialectical situation we count as theism. 

2. An Adequate Concept of God 
This brings us naturally to the question of what we might consider to be an adequate concept of God, whether or not we wish to argue for the existence of such a being. Some profound remarks were made on this by J. N. Findlay in his article (‘Can God's Existence be Disproved?’ (Findlay 1949). The heathen may worship stocks and stones but does not see them as merely stocks and stones. More and more adequate conceptions of God still portray God as limited in various respects. A fully adequate conception of God, Findlay said, would see God as not only unlimited in various admirable properties but also as a necessarily existing being. Thus ‘There is one and only one God’ would have to be a logically necessary truth. Now logic, he held, is tautologous and without ontological commitment. So God's necessary existence would have to be something different from logical necessity. The trouble is how to see what this could be. It might be replied that there are non-trivial necessary existential propositions in mathematics, such as ‘There are infinitely many primes’ which implies of course ‘the number 7 exists’. (We can ignore the unhelpful ‘Something exists’ which is allowed by standard first order logic purely for convenience as few would need to apply logic to discourse about an empty universe for which in any case there are separate rules for determining validity or otherwise.) It is well known that Frege in his Foundations of Arithmetic claimed to reduce arithmetic to logic. However in effect he was using a free logic without ontological commitment. Claims to reduce set theory (and so analysis) to logic are of course even more problematic. Would it help towards an adequate conception of God if we said that God has the sort of existence or non-existence that prime numbers have? One might say ‘not much’. In any case it is dangerous to talk of types of existence because it treats existence as though it was a property. At the time that he wrote his article Findlay was following the logical positivist line that logic and mathematics are alike tautologous. In the case of mathematics this can be seriously questioned. Also most theists would say that prime numbers are too abstract to be compared to God, though perhaps not John Leslie who has argued that God is a principle that brings value into existence (Leslie 1979 and 1989). We are still left with Findlay's challenge as to what a conception of God as a necessary being could be. One thing that will not differentiate the theist from the atheist is to say that God, if he exists, is necessary in the sense of not being dependent on anything else for his existence. The atheist will say that the universe fits this bill because the universe contains everything that there is and so is not caused by anything else. It is indeed hard to see what an adequate conception of God and his necessary existence could be. For the purposes of this article, let us explore what the relations and lack of relations between atheism and agnosticism could be. Here we shall neglect the requirement of necessary existence and in a later section we shall consider the case of a posteriori arguments for the existence of a mind-like creator of the universe. Of course without the requirement of necessity it raises the intelligent child's question ‘Who made God?’ Still, this might be regarded as inevitable but excusable in an a posteriori argument in which the hypothesis of a purposive creator is put forward and claimed to be justified much in the manner of any scientific hypothesis.
3. Agnosticism
Though there are a couple of references in The Oxford English Dictionary to earlier occurrences of the word ‘agnostic’, it seems (perhaps independently) to have been introduced by T. H. Huxley at a party in London to found the Metaphysical Society, which flourished for over a decade and to which belonged notable thinkers and leaders of opinion. Huxley thought that as many of these people liked to describe themselves as adherents of various ‘isms’ he would invent one for himself. He took it from a description in Acts 17:23 of an altar inscribed ‘to an unknown God’. Huxley thought that we would never be able to know about the ultimate origin and causes of the universe. Thus he seems to have been more like a Kantian believer in unknowable noumena than like a Vienna Circle proponent of the view that talk of God is not even meaningful. Perhaps such a logical positivist should be classified as neither a theist nor an atheist, but her view would be just as objectionable to a theist. ‘Agnostic’ is more contextual than is ‘atheist’, as it can be used in a non-theological way, as when a cosmologist might say that she is agnostic about string theory, neither believing nor disbelieving it. In this article I confine myself to the use of ‘agnostic’ in a theological context. Huxley's agnosticism seems nevertheless to go with an extreme empiricism, nearer to Mill's methods of induction than to recent discussions of the hypothetico-deductive and partly holistic aspect of testing of theories. Though we might not be able to prove the existence of God might we be able to disprove it? Many philosophers hold that the existence of an omnipotent, omniscient and good God is empirically refuted by the existence of evil and suffering, and so would be happy to be called atheists rather than agnostics.Of course the existence of a non-benevolent creator God would not be so refutable and atheism would have to depend on arguments other than that of the mere existence of evil. More commonly the theist will continue to include benevolence in the concept of God and attempt to deal with the problem of evil with the help of various auxiliary or even ad hoc hypotheses or considerations, much as a scientist may attempt, often successfully, to shore up against empirical refutation a previously well tested theory. Bayesian considerations may determine rationally, though roughly, the appropriate degree of belief or unbelief. 

4. The Ethics of Belief 
It is therefore useful, at this point of the discussion, to consider some contentions brought forward by the mathematician W. K. Clifford in his well known paper ‘The Ethics of Belief’ first published in 1877 (Clifford 1999). It might be said that beliefs are not actions and so are not subject to our will, but Clifford gave good examples of how we can induce expedient or comforting beliefs in ourselves. Of course we might also think of the argument of Pascal's wager where he advises the doubter in the Christian religion to frequent the company of priests and other committed Catholics, to avoid reading sceptical books, and to use holy water and other psychological expedients, so as to induce in himself belief in the Catholic faith. Clifford gives some telling examples of how we can induce in ourselves beliefs which run counter to the evidence before us. One is of a ship owner who makes a fortune by transporting emigrants in old and unseaworthy ships. He toys with the idea that he should not allow one such ship to sail, and instead to have it overhauled and refitted. He talks himself into allowing the ship to sail. He reflects that up to the present the ship has survived bad storms. If religious he may turn to Providence. Spurred on by greed and self-interest he induces in himself the comfortable conviction that all will be well, but in fact the ship and all aboard are lost. We can agree that the ship owner's action in inducing the optimistic belief was morally highly reprehensible. Clifford makes the further remark that even if by good luck the ship did reach port we should still regard his optimistic belief as morally reprehensible. In fact, Clifford urges, it is always reprehensible to believe on insufficient grounds. Clifford was not a philosophical sceptic about induction . He was an empiricist who assumed the uniformity of nature, belief in which was justified by the success of science and so, as he thought, not contrary to his own prohibition. Philosophers may think this too quick. However he rightly was not inclined to say, as a naïve follower of K. R. Popper might, that scientific theories can only be refuted, never established. It would surely be absurd to say that we now know no more than Galileo did. Alan Musgrave has astutely remarked that even if we agree that the fact that a theory has so far survived severe tests does not provide a reason for the hypothesis, nevertheless it does provide a reason for believing the hypothesis (Musgrave 1974). Philosophers of science now put more stress on the hypothetico-deductive method, in the partially holistic nature of theories, and the way in which justification of theories depends on the coherence of our beliefs. Science can even improve its own methodology, so that the nature of science is well captured by Neurath's simile of scientists as like sailors on a boat which they build and repair while still at sea. Clifford's contention about the reprehensibility of believing without or against the evidence still stands. Thus there are people who believe the Old Testament literally and with whom it is impossible to talk about biological evolution or modern cosmology. They often say explicitly that they will read and believe only what they find it comforting to read and believe. To give a correct and fully general account of the nature of justified belief is difficult and inevitably controversial. Furthermore, though the notion of knowledge as justified true belief runs up against ingenious counterexamples proposed by Edmund Gettier (Gettier 1963) , nevertheless for the present purpose of distinguishing atheism from agnosticism it is good enough to treat knowledge as at least justified true belief. Clifford was of course concerned with the ethics of belief, not of knowledge, and indeed the latter does not make much sense, since ‘know’ is a success word. Later we shall look at the question of whether we should say that an atheist is someone who claims to know that there is no God or someone who at any rate believes this. Clifford goes on to say that even if the ship in his example had by good fortune not foundered in the storms and high seas, or perhaps by good fortune encountered only calm seas and pleasant winds, the ship owner's cultivation of his unreasonable and dishonest belief would still have been dishonourable and reprehensible. Here he speaks like a virtue ethicist but the view can be consequentialist, since Clifford stresses that although some may derive comfort from their credulity, this credulity would tend to spread or be reinforced and so would in general have unfortunate consequences. Of course that there is no evidence for God's existence is not necessarily evidence for God's nonexistence, though it might be if we had reason for thinking that if God existed there would be evidence for this. However this may be, Clifford was adamant in describing the consequential evils of believing without evidence. Indeed he cast his net widely when he said that it is not only the leaders of men who have the duty of proportioning belief to evidence. ‘Every rustic’, he says, ‘who delivers in the village alehouse his slow, infrequent sentences, may help to kill or keep alive the fatal superstitions which clog his race’. It is undeniable that many, perhaps most, theists do not even attempt to reconcile their belief in God or in the tenets of a particular religion with philosophical arguments or with plausibility in the light of total science. On the other hand many scientists, especially some physicists and cosmologists, and some philosophers, do claim to believe in God because of evidence, namely, because of the fact that there are simple laws of nature and even more so on the apparent so-called ‘fine tuning’ of the fundamental physical constants which will be discussed shortly. Perhaps, however, most theists believe in God simply because their parents and teachers have told them that he exists. And perhaps the parents and teachers believe in God because of what their parents and teachers told them. Must we always refuse to believe because of authority? Obviously not. Science is an interactive social phenomenon and depends heavily on testimony, as indeed does our commonsense and historical knowledge. We can think of the scientific community as a vast interconnected brain. Bits of scientific testimony can be checked and experiments repeated. Clifford gives the example of a chemical fact for which, being no chemist himself, he relies on the testimony of a chemist. He knows nothing against the chemist's character and he knows the professional training of the chemist. Though he has never himself verified the chemical proposition or even seen an experiment which verified it, nevertheless , Clifford says, the proposition is never beyond the reach of experimental checking. Also the experiment may have been actually performed by his informant, though the informant may just have relied on other well credentialled chemists. It could be contended that Clifford was too verificationist here. Beliefs can be very conjectural but arguably plausible in the light of our more directly tested scientific hypotheses. There is perhaps a grey area between well tested or testable science and purely transcendent theology and metaphysics. Let us turn to consider an already mentioned example of this. 

5. The Grey Area: Example of the So-called Fine Tuning of the Fundamental Constants of Nature 
The fundamental physical and cosmological constants seem to be finely tuned (in a sense that does not immediately imply the existence of a fine tuner) so that if they were even quite slightly different in relation to one another a universe such as ours with galaxies, stars, planets, life and minds could not have existed. Not only is the range of suitable variation very small in the case of individual pairs of constants, but this is so for many such pairs, and so the a priori probability of a universe like ours is (to speak loosely) almost infinitesimal. Some philosophers, theologians, and (in their less professional moments) physicists and cosmologists have seen this fact of the very small prior probability of a universe like ours as indicating a use of scientific method as a route to theism. (See some of the articles, pro and con in Manson 2003.) The probability of the fine tuning is raised by the hypothesis of a creator God arranging the constants so as to permit the evolution of life and consciousness in which it is assumed that God has an interest. Suppose that we judge hypothesis h to provide the best explanation (supposing it true) of empirical or already accepted facts e . If so we think it rational to believe h or at least to take it very seriously. In mainstream science if an hypothesis is accepted as the best explanation (where ‘best’ can include various virtues such as simplicity and comprehensiveness as well as a certain empirical adequacy) there is a good hope that in the future fresh independent tests of the hypothesis may be possible so that the hypothesis may become part of mainstream science. The fine tuning argument for theism seems to be one that must be left as without prospect of becoming part of mainstream science. Nevertheless it is not clear that a philosopher or theologian who supported her belief in theism by such an argument to the best explanation would be ipso facto reprehensible or dishonourable in the way that Clifford thought. She does think that she is arguing from evidence, namely the fine tuning. A follower of Clifford might object if there was no philosophical discussion of rival explanations or of the application here of Bayes' theorem in the theory of probability. But as with most philosophical disputes the issues are complex and there may be trading off of rival plausibilities and implausibilities. This is no place to try adequately to discuss the fine tuning argument but let us consider two questions. One is about the type of argument that is put forward. The other is the issue of partial belief. The fine tuning argument has the merit of having the form of a perfectly normal pattern of scientific argument. Thus to some extent it may appeal to those who think of plausibility in the light of total science as a main pointer to metaphysical truth. After all, it will be contended, scientific method is the only reliable and indubitably successful and self-correcting method of attaining knowledge (pure mathematics perhaps excepted). In the fine tuning argument God is postulated to explain the fine tuning. It is asked how else a universe like ours (suitable for life and consciousness) could have arisen. Various objections could be made. The Bayesian argument is from the very easily proved equation which says that if h is a hypothesis, e the evidence, and k the relevant background information, then the probability of h given e & k is equal to the probability of e given h & k divided by the probability of e given k. The ‘e given k’ in the denominator reflects the fact that antecedently surprising evidence is best, as is the case with the fine tuning argument, and the ‘given h & k’ in the numerator reflects the fact that the antecedent probability of e given the hypothesis and the background assumptions should be high or near one, as is usually the case in argument to the best explanation. Should such an argument make us espouse theism? Not necessarily, because h, the theistic hypothesis might be so initially implausible that though e, the fine tuning, increases the probability of h, it increases it to only a small value. In assessing the plausibilities it is worth recalling that the fine tuning appeals to God's purposes, should he exist, and to his supposed interest in minds and particularly in consciousness. This might strike some of us as anthropocentric, or in view of the probability of life and consciousness elsewhere in the universe, perhaps psychocentric. Of course science has got less and less anthropocentric and perhaps psychocentricity might have lost its attractions also. In prescientific ages we appealed to the purposes of ancestors or gods, and small children seem naturally to be satisfied with explanations in terms of purpose. Similarly a saddle between hills has been said to be a tribal ancestor's fish weir, though perhaps this is not believed too literally. Yet a neuroscientific account of a particular purpose must be extraordinarily complex involving of millions or tens of millions of neurons and their multiple interconnections. Appeal to God's purposes might well conceal even more complexity. Thus the contemporary form of the teleological argument, from the fine tuning, though unaffected by the Darwinian theory as Paley's was, makes a departure from scientific methodology. Perhaps Plato's Socrates in the Phaedo may have to some extent set science off on the wrong track when he extolled purposive explanations at the expense of physical ones. Still the fine tuning argument with its argument to the best explanation and with its holism is in some ways closer to scientific method than the very restrictive though salutary empiricism of Mill and Huxley and probably Clifford. In the light of these considerations let us consider the appropriateness or otherwise of someone (call him ‘Philo’) describing himself as a theist, atheist or agnostic. I would suggest that if Philo estimates the various plausibilities to be such that on the evidence before him the probability of theism comes out near to one he should describe himself as a theist and if it comes out near zero he should call himself an atheist, and if it comes out somewhere in the middle he should call himself an agnostic. There are no strict rules about this classification because the borderlines are vague. If need be, like a middle-aged man who is not sure whether to call himself bald or not bald, he should explain himself more fully. This of course assumes that, unlike Huxley, he does not wish to use ‘ism’ words at all. Gilbert Ryle once wrote an article against, though not absolutely against, ‘ism’ words (Ryle 1935), but here he was mainly objecting to schools of philosophy as were common in Germany, so that people would attach themselves too blindly to some great figure in the past, or to some influential contemporary professor. Sometimes , at least in social contexts, it can be misleading not to say ‘yes’ or ‘no’ if some believer asks ‘Are you an atheist?’ Forthrightness can override a too precious concern for complete accuracy. Here it has been assumed that Philo regards ‘God exists’ (vagueness apart) as an intelligible sentence to which truth or falsity can be ascribed. If he thinks that the conception of deity is so obscure or so permissive that no truth value can be ascribed to ‘God exists’, perhaps he should extend the notion of ‘atheist’ to cover his position also. ‘Agnostic’ might suggest that there is something to be agnostic about. In the above discussion I have used the argument from the fine tuning as an example of something in the grey area between science and metaphysics. There may be other plausible arguments for theism that Philo could consider, and together with further applications of the Bayesian formula the plausibility might be increased in every case. Nevertheless it still might be quite small even in toto. I am assuming that all the arguments are from plausibility considerations and so can reinforce one another. Of course if the arguments fail because of faults in pure logic, then they do not reinforce one another. The conjunction of several logically bad arguments is indeed no better than one logically bad argument. Even if various philosophers or theologians use the word ‘God’ in different ways and are such that their words are quite unintelligible then they can hardly be said to defend theism. As I have suggested, a logical positivist such as the young A. J. Ayer (Ayer 1936) would have at least been less misleading if he called himself an atheist rather than an agnostic. He neither believes nor disbelieves in God, like the agnostic, but he does not think, as I take it that someone who called himself an agnostic would, that God either exists or does not exist but he does not know which. 

6. Philosophical vs. Pragmatic Reasons for Preferring the Term ‘Agnostic’ 
As was hinted earlier, a person may call herself an agnostic, as Huxley did, because of questionable philosophical motives. Huxley thought that propositions about the transcendent, though possibly meaningful, were empirically untestable. We have seen that it is unclear that the conclusion of the fine tuning argument is untestable. One can at least compare it with other and non-theistic hypotheses. Thus there are conjectures that there are many universes, so many of them that is not surprising that there should be some among them in which the constants of physics allow for the possibility of life, and if so our universe must be one of them. Some cosmologists give independent grounds for thinking that new universes are spawned out of the back of black holes. Others think that there are independent grounds for thinking of a single huge Universe that has crystallised out into various universe sized regions each with randomly different values for the fundamental constants. Some such speculations get some support (it has been suggested) from string theory. Though such speculations are at present untestable and should be taken with a grain of salt, one or another may well one day be absorbed into a testable theory. It must be left to cosmologists and mathematical physicists to go into the pros and cons here, but they are mentioned here to indicate a grey area between the testable and the untestable. Some scientists when canvassing these issues of philosophical theology may prefer to call themselves ‘agnostics’ rather than ‘atheists’ because they have been over impressed by a generalised philosophical scepticism or by a too simple understanding of Popper's dictum that we can never verify a theory but only refute it. Such a view would preclude us from saying quite reasonably that we know that the Sun consists largely of hydrogen and helium. When we say ‘I know’ we are saying something defeasible. If later we discover that though what we said was at the time justified, it nevertheless turned out to be false, we would say ‘I thought I knew but I now see that I didn't know’. Never or hardly ever to say ‘I know’ would be to deprive these words of their usefulness, just as the fact that some promises have to be broken does not deprive the institution of promising of its legitimacy. Another motive whereby an atheist might describe herself as an agnostic is purely pragmatic. In discussion with a committed theist this might occur out of mere politeness or in some circumstances from fear of giving even more offence. Samuel Butler, though a complete unbeliever in the doctrines of Christianity, in the preface to one of his books Erewhon Revisited (Butler 1932) described himself as the broadest of broad churchmen. That is, I take it that broad churchmen often were unbelievers, but treated the doctrine as mere myth suitable for literal consumption by the local yokels in the interests of social stability. It is unclear to me whether or not Butler was sympathetic to a very abstract sort of theism. Some may call themselves ‘agnostics’ rather than ‘atheists’ merely because they are equally repelled by the fanaticism associated with some forms of theism and by the boring obsessiveness of what Hilary Putnam has called ‘the village atheist’. (Contrast, however, Clifford's view of the matter and also the example of the radical and intellectual tinker, Mr. Shaw, in Butler's powerful novel The Way of All Flesh.) Still, these considerations are perhaps more a matter for sociologists than for philosophers.


Bibliography
Alexander, Samuel, 1927, Space, Time and Deity, London: Macmillan.
Ayer, A.J., 1936, Language, Truth and Logic, London: Gollancz, 2nd edition, 1946.
Bradley, M.C., 2001, ‘The Fine-Tuning Argument’, Religious Studies, 37: 451–66.
Bradley, M.C., 2002, ‘The Fine-Tuning Argument: The Bayesian Version’, Religious Studies, 38: 375–404.
Broad, C.D., 1923, Scientific Thought, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Butler, Samuel, 1932, Erewhon and Erewhon Revisited, London: J.M. Dent.
Clifford, W.K., 1999, ‘The Ethics of Belief (1877)’, in The Ethics of Belief and other Essays, Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.
Findlay, J.N., 1955, ‘Can God's Existence be Disproved?,’ in Flew and MacIntyre 1955, with replies by G.E. Hughes and A.C.A. Rainer and final comment by Findlay.
Flew, A. and MacIntyre, A. (eds.), 1955, New Essays in Philosophical Theology, London: S.C.M. Press.
Frege, G., 1980, Foundations of Arithmetic, J.L. Austin (trans.), Oxford: Blackwell.
Gettier, E.L., 1963, ‘Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?’ Analysis, 23: 121–3.
Grice, H.P., 1989, Studies in the Way of Words, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Huxley, T.H., 1895, Collected Essays: Volume 5, London: Macmillan.
Leslie, John, 1979, Value and Existence, Oxford: Blackwell.
Leslie, John, 1989, Universes, London: Routledge.
Levine, Michael P., 1994, Pantheism: A Non-Theistic Concept of Deity, London: Routledge.
Manson, Neil A. (ed.), 2003, God and Design, London: Routledge.
Martin, Michael (ed.), 2006, The Cambridge Companion to Atheism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Musgrave, Alan, 1974, ‘The Objectivism of Popper's Epistemology’ with Popper's Reply, in Schilpp (ed.) 1974, Volume 2.
Ryle, G., 1935, ‘Taking Sides In Philosophy’, Philosophy, 12: 317–32.
Schilpp, P.A. (ed.), 1974, The Philosophy of Karl Popper, La Salle, IL: Open Court.
Smart, J.J.C. and Haldane, John, 2003, Atheism and Theism, Oxford: Blackwell, 2nd edition.
Smart, J.J.C., 1981, ‘Physicalism and Emergence’, Neuroscience, 6: 109–13.
Whitehead, A.N., 1929, Process and Reality, London: Cambridge University Press.


Tuesday, July 5, 2011

Goody goody mullah


Once upon a time in a land called boneland , people live their life as usual , some of them go to work , some of them go to mosque ,some of them go to bars and some of them playing with themselves all the time .
In boneland they call the people who play with themselves "Mullah" , Mullahs where everywhere , and they were the most unhappy people of boneland , because everbody in boneland has a life and was doin something ,except them ... not because nobody let them do anything , because no matter what they have they wanted something they couldn't have and that was a life ...
So they were always thinking about the ways that they could get a life as they were playing with themselves . 
One day ,one of the mullahs that they called " the goody goody mullah " suddenly thought of something , goody goody mullah was one of the worse mullahs , but because he was a witch he made a beautiful image for him self ,and that s why people called him "goody goody mullah"
any way , one day that goody goody mullah was very busy playing with himself , and in a same time he was thinking of a way to get a life , he thought of something ,... he told it to other mullahs and they were all impressed with that idea .
they made a big , a very very big pulpit for him , he climed and climed up until he reached the top of the pulpit , and from there he told people of boneland "people of boneland , are you happy with your lives ?" at first nobody listened to him that much , some minded their own business , and some siad "yes , we are" , and then he asked "why are you happy with your lives ?" so , more people get interested , because they ask themselves "are we really happy ?" the goody goody mullah sees that people are starting to notice him , so he asked again "why are you not happier ? why are you have to work to be happy ?"
people of boneland were greedy and start to ask themselves "yeah , we want to be happier and we don't wanna work too !" so they yelled "what should we do ?" and the goody goody mullah says : "you can be happier , you can have life and still doing nothing but to play with yourselves" ... now everybody start to attention , and start to think "why not ? we deserve that" . but there were some bad people who didn't want to be happier so they yelled "no , we are happy , and you can not be happier and still play with yourself" but the goody goody mullah says yes you can , and then stand up and said whoever wants to be happy I can show you the way but for that you have to get rid of those bad peoples who do not want to be happier and since they exist it can not be done " so the people of boneland start to kill those bad people .
after that the goody goody mullah said " the first step is not to sin , and to be able to do that you have to close your eyes , because the eyes are the instruments of sin ,so everybody have o do that except mullahs because they are different" so everybody closed their eyes , and who ever opened his eyes after that , the mullahs took his eyes out , and everybody were agree with that , cause nobody wants to be "not more happy" because of somebody else . 
after that the goody goody mullah said " the next step to not sin is to not talk , because talking is bad and it s the work of evil " and since everybody afraid of evil they stoped talking , and whoever talked since then the mullahs took their tounge off with a pincer , and everybody were happy with that because no body wants to be "not more happy" because of somebody else .
after that the goody goody mullah said you can keep your ears because it s the only way you can hear him and told them try to not sin with your ears or mullahs have to cut them off as well , now the next step is to put your blood in glasses , because the blood is the color of evil and because of that the evil can make you do bad stuffs , so everybody agreed with that , and they put their bloods in glasses and gave them to mullahs to keep it for them , because the mullahs were the only ones that couldn't be tempt by evil . but it was n't because of that , it was because the blood was the life that mullahs didn't have ,and now with blood they have !
and then the goody mullah said start playing with yourself until you feel happier and whoever played with himself the most will be happier the most , so people start to play with themselves as hard as they could .and after a while they couldn't think of anything except playing with themselves and they forgot about the life they had .
now years passed and the goody goody mullah is in heaven with 70 virgins and now a better mullah called "the dragon boy" and his sidekick "the sheep" is sitting on the pulpit ...


thanks for watching ladies and gentlemen , have nice happy life .



Thursday, June 16, 2011



Here s an old one from back then : 


Mama can you see through me ?
Mama can you cut through these walls ?
Will you bring a light ?
Will you kiss my sores ?
Can you see my lips ?
O mama I can n't see .
Can you feel my face ?
I wanna see my self .
Can you see my hands ?
O mama somebody s sobbing .
Can you hear my preys ?
When can I go out and play ?
Mama , say something .
Why I should n't tell anybody ?
Am I bleeding ?
Ooo , I m cold .
Mama , put your hand on my chest please .
I m sleepy mama ...

Wednesday, June 15, 2011

   Hi , some of you may remember me , I posted here before under the name "the owl" ...


   Anyway it s been a long time and I m sorry about unexpected and sudden absent , something came up real quick , unexpected , unbelievable and I had to live in darkness in shadow ,be afraid of daylight ,be afraid of night , and after a while I had to delete any trace that left of me and finally leave the old country , my home , my friends , my family ...


   For a person that lived all of his/her life under the shadow of security under the shadow of freedom it s hard to believe how is it possible that something like that happen to an average person . unless that person is a serial killer or someone with very high anti society , anti government activities or in simple words "a very bad example !" ... and yes that s what they call us "a very bad example" . that s why it happen to me or people like me , but for being a bad example what should you do ? how bad you have to be so they call you a bad example ? how bad a bad example must be that they want it to be out , they want it to be dead , to be not to be !


    Let s talk bout it , how you live you life ? let s say you r an average young man ,an atheist , who works at office , you like to go to a good college someday, you may have your plans to get married with your girlfriend someday! and you love to hangout with your friends and gf at weekends and you like movies and some old school band like mmm lets say Guns n Roses ! probably you simply woke up every morning , go to work , may have a small talk about everyday stuffs with your colleagues , go back home ,have a little rest , listen to some music , sometimes watch a movie at home with your friends or girlfriend , some times hang out at a bar , sometimes playing your guitar ... sometimes you may have more going on in your life sometimes less ,but I think it s the most simplest image an average young man right ? now let s see how is a same person with same tastes and hopes lives in Iran ...
   You wake up at morning , you wanna shave but you remember let s not ! why ? because as much as you hate your beard but you hope you can have a little raise with it ! how ? it s simple in Iran ! you have beard ,you are mostly like a good person , a man of GOD !. you shave every morning ? you r mostly like a bad person cuz a man of god wont shave his beard because their prophet didn't ! and the worst thing is when you shave you may like the western culture and that s bad because the west does not like our regime , and whoever dislike our regime is against god ! because our regime is the only true kingdom of GOD ! anyway that goes your shaving ! 
you go to work , you may have a conversation with your colleagues , but it s not that simple you have to worry about what you may say , you have to be careful not to talk about your very own opinion , your point of view about the religion , about the regime and about anything related to them , why ? because somehow the people who works for regime always hear you and if they hear you and if you r lucky you will never get a raise at your work and you will stock in your post forever , and if you r not lucky enough and you recognize as a person who has deviant thoughts you will be out of job soon ! anyway you finish your work time , you comeback home and want to have a little peace ,  can you play your favorite music ? no !!! cuz the Guns n Roses is the music of evil ! and if the neighbors complain about it to police you will be in a very very big problem NOT because of the loudness because of the music and the propagation of western culture among the youth ! so you decide to watch a movie instead ,but you r sick of the Islamic televisions and so called Islamic movies and you wanna watch another movie . does it allowed ? no ! you only can watch the foreign moves that your regime allows you to ! and that the movies that they censored the hell out of it ,movies that they even censored any kiss scene between a man and a woman , the movies that they censored any so called nudity ! nudity ? not the nudity you think ! ANYTHING ANYTHING that shows below the neck and above the ankle is nudity ! you don believe it ? I can show you censorship in Iran media ... anyway you can not watch it online cause most of the sites is censored because of the so called cultural differences , sites like youtube , like facebook , like and lot more , till 2009 as they said they filtered 5 million web pages , and even if you find a webpage that is not filtered or if you pass the filers somehow and get access to any site you want the connection speed is way slower to let you watch anything online , anyway , you manage to somehow find some illegal sources to buy some DVDs from , and you wanna watch them , you can not call your friends every time cause the neighbors will complain about it to police not because you disturb them because they do not like some young people to hangout together because they may do some none-Islamic things ! like drinking alcohol and worse there could be a girl with them ! and that s a bad example for their child !
so by now i think you now why you can not call your girlfriend either ! so good or bad it will pass , the night will finish and another will start like that , and after a while you decide to see your beloved girlfriend ! you certainly can not call her to come to your house that easy you have to watch out for neighbors ! it s not their business but in a Islamic culture any connection between a man and a woman who are not related by blood or not MARRIED is ILLEGAL ! it s against Islamic culture and it s against the will of god ! so if they call the police and police come to your place and find you with a girl you will be in a deep problem and you can say goodbye to your hope to get a raise at your job and ... so I think you can imagine that in this situation you can not go out that easily , you have to hide from police and get me start on f*** "baij" the army of god ! the arm of Islam ! 
   I hope i could draw a simple picture of Iran , in a situation a so called Islamic culture that make your life a living hell for small things like what I just said , Imagine you are an Atheist , you don believe in what they told you , can you imagine that ? you never can talk about it freely you never can not talk about with all your friends , if anybody ask you about your believes you have to lie you absolutely have to lie , why ? because in Islam if anybody born "Moslem" and deny his/her religion , they call him/her an apostate , and the penalty of an apostate is death , so if anybody ask you ,you are a proud Moslem ! 
    What about the music you ask ? no no no , you can not play any music you want ! why ? because in Islam ,ANY MUSIC THAT MAKES YOU FEEL DELIGHT IS A MATERIAL AND PHYSICAL PLEASURE AND ANY PLEASURE THAT IS NOT BY GOD's WILL IS A BIG SIN !!!
the most funny part is even when they show a music that they agreed with on TV they will not show the instruments and players because it s not good ! why ? because it may tempt you to learn and play music and if you learn to play music you may play a something that is a sin ! 
so you r not allowed to play anything with your instrument ! so forget about playing your guitar either ..


   So what happen to me ? why am i a bad example ? how bad i was that they want to put me in jail , how bad were my friends that went into jail ?!
   I tell you what , as I said music is almost is an illegal thing , because first of all when you like western culture you are a bad person because west doesn t like our regime , so they are against the great ISLAM and the GREAT GOD so they call the west the GREAT SATAN ! so when you don like their rules so you like the west ! and when you like the west you mostly hate Islam so you hate god and that s enough to be a walking dead in Iran , second of all ,I explained how is it possible to do a very great sin when you play music ! and band like Guns n Roses , or worse ,bands like Metallica that their music is a bit odd for every first time listener , in Islamic opinions is without a doubt a SATANIC voice that sent by Satan himself to destroy the minds of youth , now you Imagine you are an Atheist who hates the regime , who loves metal music , who hate Islamic culture , who hates their so called God , who hates their Mullahs and all your life you hide your identity , you hide who you really are even that you know you r not a bad person even if you can not hurt an small animal , just because your opinions and thought is different from what the damned regime want you to have ,and now just because of JUST BECAUSE of being at an underground metal concert , you are at the center of the ruthless government agents attention , and they put most of your friends in jail just because of their underground music activities ,and now they come after you ! 
   That s my sin ! that s why i had to left everything i had everything i worked my whole life on and worse i had to leave behind my beloved family and friends and run ...
   sorry for my bad english ...